the star property
the * property
In two separate meetings, we made judicious use of what Sidney Morris, in his textbook Topology without Tears, calls the *
(pronounced ‘star’) property. This property focuses on subsets of R
(the set of real numbers), and we can use it to prove many important claims about the topological structure of R
and subsets of R
.
A subset
$S \subset \mathbb{R}$
is said to be open in the euclidean topology on$\mathbb{R}$
if it has the following property: (*
) For each$x \in S$
, there exist$a, b \in \mathbb{R}$
with$a < b$
such that$s \in (a,b) \subseteq S$
.
Some practice is recommended to get the hang of this definition, so let’s jump right in.
euclidean toplogy
We have *
and want to show that $(\mathbb{R}, \tau)$
satisfies the axioms for a toplogogical space. As a reminder, these axioms are (restated with direct reference to $\mathbb{R}$
without any loss of generality):
- the complete set
$\mathbb{R}$
and the empty set$\emptyset$
are members of$\tau$
- any union of members of
$\tau$
is also a member of$\tau$
- any finite intersection of members of
$\tau$
is also a member of$\tau$
Recall, also, that $\tau$
is simply a collection of subsets of $\mathbb{R}$
.
Proof that 1 holds true for $(\mathbb{R},\tau)$
Pick any real number x
. Subtract 1
from x
to get a
. Add 1
to x
to get b
. Convince yourself that x
lies somewhere ‘between’ a
and b
.
Now, $(a, b)$
is an open interval and a subset of $\mathbb{R}$
. This satisfies the definition of *
precisely, namely,
and so, by definition, $(a, b)$
is open in $(\mathbb{R}, \tau)$
. Do this for all $x \in \mathbb{R}$
and we show that $\mathbb{R} \in \tau$
.
You can say that for some $y \notin \mathbb{R}$
, there is precisely one interval $\emptyset$
where the *
property holds; therefore $\emptyset \in \mathbb{R}$
as well.
Proof that 2 holds true for $(\mathbb{R},\tau)$
Recall that $\tau$
is simply a collection of sets, so we can easily choose some subcollection, call it A
. In fact, we can make many such choices; so, each time we choose a unique subcollection of $\tau$
, we can ‘tag’ it (‘index’ is the correct term for this), so we have $A_i$
. All this means is that we can have a collection of subcollections of $\tau$
, and we can keep track of which subcollection we’re talking about using the indices.
To prove the second axiom for $(\mathbb{R},T)$
, we can use the *
property again on this family of indexed subcollections $\{ A_i \}$
.
Pick any real number x
from a set built from the union of subsets in $A_k$
, which is a specific member of the family $\{ A_i \}$
. We then have x
as a member of the subcollection A_k
. Now we chose each A
such that $A \in T$
. There must then be some $a,b \in \mathbb{R}$
where the statement
holds true. By induction, this must hold true in general for the family { A_i }
, meaning
holds true. This again is the *
property, and so we’ve shown all unions of any subcollection of $\tau$
belongs to $\tau$
.
Proof that 3 holds true for $(\mathbb{R},\tau)$
At this point, we have a bit of freedom – believe it or not, things are getting easier. Pick any pair of subsets $A, B \in \tau$
. Pick some y
from the intersection of A
and B
: $y \in A \cap B$
. By definition of set intersection, $y \in A$
. Using a similar trick as above in proving the second axiom holds on $(\mathbb{R},\tau)$
, we can show
Moreover, y ∈ B
by definition of set intersection, and so
Almost there! If we have some number e
larger than both a
and c
, and we have some number f
smaller than both b
and d
; then $e < y < f$
. Hence,
The intersection – which is, after all, any pair of subset from $\tau$
– has the *
property.
extreme generality
The extreme generality involved in this proof caught me off gaurd the first time. But if you think about it, we need an extremely general approach to making a claim about the topological structure of the real numbers – \mathbb{R}
is uncountably large! That’s why the proof is so careful to pick, with as little specificity as possible, “any” real number, or “any” set from a subcollection, or “any” pair of subsets to test whether or not it has the *
property. If we are able to make this selection with as few restrictions as possible, then the property demonstrated on that selection “carries through” to any other selection we could have made – which is to say any and all open sets.
Topology is like that; its extreme generality allows you to make very careful determinations on the nature of the entire space at once.
Demostrating the ‘Openness’ of Subsets of $\mathbb{R}$
This follows proposition 2.2.1 from Topology without Tears.
A subset
$S \subset \mathbb{R}$
is open if and only if it is a union of open intervals.
This claim goes in two directions (“if and only if”); so its strength will be very useful.
Demonstrate S
is an open set
Assume for the proof that S
is a union of open intervals. We construct it with the help of indices i
, giving us
Luckily, we’ve already proven this above. This immediately gives us S
as an open set.
Demonstrate S
is a union of open intervals
Assume for the proof that S
is an open set. Pick some x
from S
. We’ll use the same trick as above to select an interval (a,b)
, so
Be careful! The temptation here is to say, “use the *
property and we’re done”. Yes, we have shown the *
property in this case but only in this case! There has been a subtle shift in language that ( if you’re really paying incredibly close attention ) should tip us off that we’ve restricted our selection of x
. We’ve chosen “some” not “any” x
, and thus we have to justify extending the *
property generally across the set S
.
The two following step will justify the extension for us.
Demonstrate all x
is contained in some interval
Pick any x
from S
. Then we get $x \in (a,b) \subseteq S$
, making us happy. This maneuver is becoming more natural for us.
Demonstrate all intervals contains some x
Pick any x
from a union of all open intervals. Then x
belongs to some open interval (at least one). Then x
belongs to S
.
S
is an open set
Why these extra steps? Another subtlty in language: $S = \cup(a_i,b_i)$
is a strong claim; before we may only have claimed that the relation ⊆
rather than =
holds for S
. ( Recall that the precise meaning of ⊆
is that the set on the left of the symbol is either equal to or a subset of the set on the right of the symbol. This is analogous to the arithmetic relation ≤
which is true when either the two numbers are equal or the number on the left is smaller. )
We demonstrate the *
property on some number x
of S
, generalize it for S
, and then generalize it for $\cup(a_i,b_i)$
, giving us justification for =
as opposed to the weaker $\subseteq$
( which we could have satisfied much sooner).
What’s next?
From here, we can move pretty quickly into the definition of a topological basis, a neighborhood for an element in a topological space, and many concrete examples for bases on the euclidiean topology. But let’s let the approach of these proofs soak in first!